SECTION III. MARC-WOGAU'S EXAMINATION OF CERTAIN ARGUMENTS FOR ALTERNATIVE TIIEORIES.

      Marc-Wogau does not attempt directly either to prove his own views or to refute alternative views. What he does is to examine and try to refute the main arguments which have been given in support of a certain important alternative view. Since that alternative is incompatible with his own, arguments for the former are ipso facto arguments against the latter. So this part of the book is in effect an attempt to refute certain widely accepted arguments which, if valid, would be fatal to his theory.

      All forms of the alternative in question involve the following proposition. 'In no case is the object which is visually prehended a physical object.' Let us call this Proposition P. If that is true, it follows that no physical object is ever 'seen', in the sense of visually prehended. But it is an essential point of Marc-Wogau's theory that, under certain conditions, the object visually prehended is a physical object, and is in fact the physical object which is being seen by the prehender.

      It is plain that attempts to prove Proposition P might in theory take either of the following forms. We might try to show

  1. that all physical objects have certain characteristics which all visual prehensa lack. E.g., that all physical objects have causal properties, and that no visual prehensa have such.
  2. That all visual prehensa have certain characteristics which all physical objects lack. E.g., that all visual prehensa are coloured in a literal non-dispositional sense, and that no physical object is coloured in that sense.
  3. That every physical object has a certain positive characteristic X which is incompatible with a certain positive characteristic Y which is possessed by all visual prehensa. E g., that every physical object is a class of particulars and every visual prehensum is a particular.
I think that in practice the most important arguments take the following form. We start with some characteristic which would generally be admitted to be part of, or to be entailed by, the definition or the commonly accepted description of a 'physical object'; and then we try to show that no visual prehensum has that property. This may be attempted either by direct inspection and generalisation, or by showing that all visual prehensa have a certain positive property which is incompatible with the one in question.

      We will now consider some of these arguments, and Marc-Wogau's answers to them.

(A) Argument frown Hallucination and Illusion.

      It has been alleged that a visual prehensum is always a mere 'colour-expanse', and never an entity to which the name of a physical object, e.g., 'penny', 'table', etc., can properly be applied. There are two main arguments for this.

      (1) It is said that the visual perception may be abnormally evoked and non-veridical. When that is the case the prehensum certainly cannot be correctly described by the name of any physical object, e.g., as a 'penny'. But the object visually prehended by a person who is actually seeing a penny need not differ in any of its visually prehended characteristics from that which is visually prehended by a person who ostensibly sees a penny but is in fact under a hallucination, produced, e.g., by hypnotic suggestion. Therefore it too cannot properly be described as a 'penny'.

      (2) Even if the perception be normally evoked, and if there be a certain physical object which is seen, that visum may be a counterfeit, e.g., a bit of wax or of cardboard made to look like a penny. The argument would then proceed on the same lines as above with suitable modifications in detail. Marc-Wogau's answer to the first argument is as follows.

      (i) At the very best 'brown, flat, roundish colour-expanse' is in many cases an inadequate description of the visual prehensum. We must substitute for it some such phrase as 'penny-looking'.

      (ii) Admittedly one must go beyond one's present visual experience in order to decide whether it is veridical or delusive; and whether, if delusive, it is wholly or only partly so. Suppose one does this, and decides that it was in fact wholly veridical. Then one would say retrospectively 'The object that I visually prehended was a penny'. One would not say 'The object that I visually prehended was penny-looking, but was not a penny; though it did stand in a certain special relation to a certain penny which was before my eyes at the time'. Suppose, on the other hand, that one decides that the perception was delusive. Then one would say retrospectively 'The object which I visually prehended was not a penny or any other physical object; it was only penny-looking, and it had not physical realitv'. The fact that I must in all cases go outside my present visual experience in order to decide whether what I visually prehended in it was a penny, or only a penny-looking non-physical object, does not suffice to show that in no case was it a penny. Marc-Wogau makes the same kind of answer, mutatis mutandis, to the second argument.

      What are we to say of these arguments, and of Marc-Wogau's answers to them? I am not satisfied either with the arguments or the answers.

      (i) Consider the transition in the first argument from the premiss 'The object visually prehended in a veridical visual perception of a penny need not differ in any of its visually prehended characteristics from the object visually prehended in a delusive ostensible perception of a penny' to the conclusion 'So it too cannot properly be described as a penny'. It seems to me that, if the qualification 'visually prehended', which I have deliberately inserted and italicised in the premise, be omitted, the premise becomes doubtful. It is not certain that the object prehended in a veridical visual perception of a penny need not differ in any of its characteristics from the object prehended in a delusive ostensible visual perception of a penny, unless we assume a certain additional premiss. This is the proposition: 'A visual prehensum cannot have any characteristics beside those which it is visually prehended as having'. But that premiss begs the question at issue. If, on the other hand, the qualification 'visually prehended' is retained in the premiss, the conclusion does not follow. For two objects, which were precisely alike in all their visually prehended characteristics, might be such that one could, and the other could not, be properly described as a 'penny'; provided that the former had, and the latter lacked, certain further characteristics, which are not and could not be visually prehended.

      (ii) As regards Marc-Wogau's criticism on the arguments I would make the following comments. In my statement of it I have carefully avoided the non-technical word 'see', and have used instead the technical term 'visually prehend'. The reason is this. What the persons who use this argument deny is that the object which we visually prehend is ever a physical object; they do not of course deny that, in the ordinary sense of 'see', we often see pennies and other physical objects. It is the argumentsforthis conclusion which Marc-Wogau is concerned to refute.

      Now his refutation seems to turn on what we should say in certain circumstances. Now in ordinary life we should not use the technical expression 'visually prehend', but the familiar word 'see'. Undoubtedly, if I persuaded myself that a certain ostensible visual perception. was normally evoked and not delusive and not the perception of a counterfeit, I should say of it: 'The object which I saw was a penny, and not merely a penny-looking object without physical existence'. But that is denied by no-one. The fact that, common-sense makes this answer, and that the answer is true, does not tell us what is the correct answer to a question which common-sense never raises, viz., 'Was that which I visually prehended in seeing the penny a physical object, and in particular was it the penny itself; or was it a penny-looking object without physical existence?'

      I would sum this up as follows. The phrases which we use in daily life to express our ostensible visual perceptions certainly suggest prima facie that, in a normally-evoked veridical visual perception, one visually prehends that physical object which one is said to see. The arguments, just considered, to prove that what we visually prehend is never a physical object are inconclusive; for they rest on the tacit assumption that a visual prehensum cannot have any characteristics beside those which it is visually prehended as having. (This assumption appears to be accepted by Marc-Wogau; for the sense in which he allows us to ascribe to a visual prehensum any characteristic which it is not prehended as having is highly Pickwickian. It amounts merely to saying that some other member of the nuclear group to which this prehensum belongs has this other characteristic.) Nevertheless, the possibility remains quite open that the prima facie suggestion of ordinary language is here misleading.

      It seems to me that we can now clearly distinguish the following three possible alternatives.

  1. That what is visually prehended in a non-delusive visual perception can properly be called a physical object, and in fact be identified with the actual visum, because it in fact has, in a quite literal and non-Pickwickian sense, a great many other characteristics beside those which it is visually prehended as having. (This may be called 'Naive Realism'. So far as I am aware, there is no conclusive argument against it.).
  2. That it can properly be called a physical object and identified with the actual visum in spite of the fact that it does not literally have any characteristics beside those which it is visually prehended as having. That is because it is one of a set of particulars which simultaneously occupy the same place and differ only abstractively from each other; because these between them have many characteristics which it lacks; and because the name 'this penny', e.g., is applied indifferently to each of these particulars. (This is what I understand to be Marc-Wogau's theory.)
  3. That it cannot properly be called a physical object, because it has no characteristics beside those which it is visually prehended as having. The experience described as 'seeing a penny' consists, even when it is completely veridical, in
    1. visually prehending, not a penny, but a penny-looking non-physical object, and
    2. basing upon that experience certain non-inferential beliefs or takings-for-granted, which go beyond anything that is being visually prehended. (This is the view held by many typical Sense-datum Theorists.)

(B) Argument from Solidity.

      It has been alleged that, although a visual prehensum may be in certain respects three-dimensional, yet it is never solid. On the other hand, the physical objects which we claim to see are solids, even when they are very flat thin ones, such as pennies or sheets of paper. Therefore, it is said, a visual prehensum can at most be part of the surface of a physical object.

      Marc-Wogau objects that the first premise of this argument involves a wrong description of the visual prehensum. I think that his example of seeing the moon on a cloudy night will best illustrate his contention. Sometimes the moon will sensibly appear as a flat disc, and sometimes as a solid sphere; and we may alternate between prehending it as flat and as solid. Neither experience is less or more immediate or purely visual than the other. In particular there is no reason to hold that, when one sees the moon as a globe, what really happens is that one prehends something as a flat disc and then bases on that experience a non-inferential belief that one is looking at a globular solid. He admits that there is a sense in which one cannot visually prehend the far side of a house or the inside of an opaque solid. But he asserts that this means only that we do not prehend the object as having a far side or an inside of a certain completely determinate character. This does not entail that we do not prehend it as having a far side or an inside of a more or less determinate character.

      In general Marc-Wogau asserts that the accounts given by supporters of the Sense-datum Theory of the spatial characteristics which a visual prehensum is prehended as having, suffer from a certain common defect. They are correct only in so far as the percipient takes up a very special mental attitude, viz., that of the draughtsman or the introspective psychologist or the optician.The careful observations of psychologists of the Gestalt School have shown that such accounts are incorrect if the percipient is in the mental attitude characteristic of ordinary practical life.

      What are we to say of these contentions? (i) Marc-Wogau is certainly right in saying that the moon, e.g., may look now flat and now convex, and that each of these spatial characteristics is visually prehended. Again, it is certain that, when I look at a cricket-ball and view it in ordinary light and in my usual mental attitude, the object which I visually prehend is prehended as convex. I do not think that this would be questioned by Moore; I am sure that it would not be questioned by Price; and it has been asserted by myself.

      (ii) This is quite consistent with the statement that, in the case of the cricket-ball, e.g., the prehensum is not prehended either

  1. as the whole of a closed outer surface, or
  2. as solid, i.e., filled with matter.

      (iii) I am not sure that Marc-Wogau wishes to maintain either (a) or (b). Perhaps all that he wishes to maintain is the following, viz.,

  1. that it is prehended as part of the outer surface of a three-dimensional object of some form or other; which may be either closed or open on the side invisible to the observer; which, if closed, may be either hollow or filled with matter; and which, even if it be open, or closed and hollow, has a certain finite thickness, and therefore a hind-surface or an inner surface of some kind or other as well as a front-surface or outer surface.

      (iv) It seems to me that (c) is the utmost that could plausibly be asserted in view of the following facts.

      (v) I should be inclined to think that (c), or something very like it, is always taken for granted by the percipient in normal waking visual perception. I suspect too that this is something primitive and not wholly explicable by experience and association; a kind of psychologically a priori schema in terms of which we interpret certain regularities among our visual and tactual experiences, and the associations to which these give rise. At any rate that seems to have been Stout's view, and his opinions on psychological and epistemological matters are not to be lightly set aside. I should, however, hesitate to say that the visual prehensum is visually prehended as having these properties, in the sense in which, e.g., it is visually prehended as round and convex and brown in the example of looking at a cricket-ball.

      But, granted all this, what follows? It seems to me that it remains obviously true that, when I look at a cricket-ball, what I see, in the sense of visually prehend, is not correctly describable as a 'cricket-ball', i.e., a solid spherical object. At the very best it is only a certain part of the outer surface of such an object. That there is a perfectly good and usual sense of the word 'see' in which I can be said to be 'seeing a cricket-ball' is true. That, however, is admitted by everyone. The question is whether what I see, in the sense of visually prehend, can be correctly described as a 'cricket-ball'. And it seems quite plain to me that the answer is No!

(C) Argument from Continuity.

      This argument is intended to show that, although it is not impossible that the visual prehensum might in some cases be identical with the actual visum, yet it would be highly unreasonable to suppose that it is so in any case. There are many alternative forms of this argument, appealing to different empirical facts; but the following example will serve to illustrate the general principle.

     Suppose that one continues to keep one's eye on the same unchanged physical object, e.g., a penny Iying on one's table, and moves about so that one views it from various distances and in various directions. One has a series of visual experiences in which the appearance of the thing changes continuously. It is alleged that, in the perceptions at one end of such a series (e.g., when one is viewing the penny at arm's length and in a direction at right angles to its surface), one is visually prehending the seen physical object itself, or at any rate a part of its outer surface. It is admitted that, in the perceptions at the other end of such a series (e.g., when one is viewing the penny from a great distance or in a very oblique direction), the visual prehensum is not the seen physical object itself or a part of its outer surface. The ground for this contention is

  1. the fact that the prehensum is prehended as having certain characteristics, e.g., ellipticity, which are incompatible with certain characteristics, e.g., roundness, which the seen physical object is known to have; and
  2. the tacitly assumed or explicitly asserted premiss that a prehensum cannot have any characteristic which is incompatible with any that it is prehended as having.

      So at some stage in such a series of visual prehensa there would be a dividing line, such that the visual prehensum on one side of it is the seen physical object or a part of its outer surface, whilst the practically indistinguishable visual prehensum on the other side of it is of a wholly different kind. In Marc-Wogau's terminology the former would exist in sense E3 and the latter only in senses E1 and E2. It is alleged that this is very improbable; and that it is therefore reasonable to hold that none of the prehensa are identical with the seen physical object or any part of its surface. And, if they are not identical with that physical object or any part of its surface, it would be unreasonable to suppose that they can be identified with any physical object or with any part of the surface of any physical object.

      I hope that the above is a fair and accurate account of this line of argument. What has Marc-Wogau to say about it? The following are the main points that he makes.

      (i) He says that the facts have been wrongly stated in certain important respects, because the persons who use the argument have ignored what psychologists call 'Phenomenal Constancy'. The facts included under that head may be summarised as follows.

  1. A physical object may continue to present precisely the same visual appearance when certain physical and physiological conditions, e.g., the distance and direction from which the observer views the object, the illumination, and so on, vary considerably.
  2. This constancy in the visual appearances holds only within certain limits of variation in the conditions.
  3. When the conditions change, and yet a certain object continues to look precisely the same in certain respects, there are always certain compensatory changes in the visual appearance either of other objects in the field of view or in certain other aspects of the visual appearance of this object. E.g., if a match-box continues to look rectangular when viewed from various directions, its orientation in the visual field will visibly alter.
  4. Constancy or inconstancy in the visual appearances under varying physical and physiological conditions depends to some extent on the mental attitude of the percipient. Constancy is most marked when his mental attitude is that of ordinary practical activity. But in other mental attitudes, such as that of the draughtsman, the optician, or the introspective psychologist, it may almost vanish.
  5. The optimal conditions for constancy are that the object should be seen from about arm's length, that it should be roughly normal to the line of vision, and that the illumination should be ordinary daylight.

      Marc-Wogau says, justly I think, that most English writers on these subjects have neglected phenomenal constancy. They have tended to confine their attention to the appearances which would be presented to a percipient who had put himself into the 'purely optical attitude'. (I suspect that, in many cases, they have not even tried seriously to examine the appearances, but have been content to infer them from geometrical considerations about the shape and size of the area of the retina affected by the light coming from the visum!) Price is the least sinful of us in this respect; but all have fallen short.

      (ii) Marc-Wogau argues that the purely intrinsic visual characteristics of a prehensum are not the decisive factor in determining whether it exists in sense E3 or only in senses E1 and E2. What is important is its relationships to other objects which exist in sense E3. So there is nothing paradoxical in the assertion that, of two prehensa which are practically indistinguishable in the intrinsic visual qualities which they are prehended as having, one is the seen physical object or a part of its surface whilst the other is not a physical object or a part of the surface of one.

      (iii) It is just a fact to be accepted that, when one is said to be looking at the same unchanged physical object from various distances and in various directions, the objects prehended under certain variations in the conditions differ only abstractively from each other whilst those prehended under certain further variations in the conditions differ qualitatively from the former and from each other. The distinction between the two sub-classes of visual prehensa is quite clear conceptually, even though there be marginal cases in which it is difficult to decide whether a certain visual prehensum is nuclear or non-nuclear.

     What are we to say of the Argument from Continuity and of Marc-Wogau's answers to it? In the first place, what precisely is the relevance of the Phenomenon of Constancy?

      I think that it is relevant in the following respects. (i) It would be very paradoxical to hold that just a single one or a finite number of visual prehensa out of a potentially infinite class of such objects, forming a continuous series in respect of their visual qualities, is identical with the seen physical object, or with some part of its surface. It is much less paradoxical to hold that every one of a certain sub-group, which is itself potentially infinite and is marked off by the fact that its members differ only abstractively from each other, is identical with the seen physical object or with some part of its surface. Now recognition of the phenomenon of constancy provides one with such an outstanding group; whilst non-recognition of it commits one either to the more paradoxical position or to the view that none of the visual prehensa should be identified with the seen physical object or with any part of its surface.

      (ii) If it were not for the phenomenon of constancy, Marc-Wogau's theory of sense-perception and the physical object would fail at the first move. For his nuclear class, consisting of visual prehensa which differ from each other only abstractively, each of which is identified with the seen physical object, would be empty.

      (iii) It must be admitted, however, that recognition of the phenomenon of constancy merely shifts the point of application of the Argument from Continuity to the boundary between the nuclear and the non-nuclear sub-classes of that group of visual prehensa, each member of which is commonly identified with the seen physical object. According to Marc-Wogau each member of the nuclear sub-class is quite correctly identified with the seen physical object. But any member of the non-nuclear sub-class is identified with it only by courtesy; strictly speaking, it should be counted only as a 'sense-datum' and not as a physical object. Yet the two sub-classes melt insensibly into each other.

      We have seen that Marc-Wogau recognizes this fact, and we have seen how he tries to deal with the argument based on it. In this connexion I would make the following remarks.

      (a) The contention that there is any fundamental intrinsic difference between members of the two sub-groups is rendered still less plausible by one of the empirical facts mentioned in connexion with the Phenomenon of Constancy. We are told, no doubt correctly, that, even with precisely the same physical and physiological conditions, the object visually prehended may be either nuclear or non-nuclear according to whether the percipient's mental attitude is of one kind or another. That is to say, it often depends on purely subjective conditions whether the prehensum shall be the seen physical object, or shall be only a 'sense-datum of' that object.

      (b) It is very important to remember that the persons who have used the Argument from Constancy had in mind a very different view of the nature of physical objects from Marc-Wogau's, and that they almost certainly never contemplated the alternative which he has put forward. Perhaps the main differences may be put as follows. They assumed, tacitly or explicitly, that the expression 'that physical object', e.g., 'that penny', denotes a single particular, which has simultaneously characteristics of many different kinds (including causal characteristics), and has every characteristic in a completely determinate form. Marc-Wogau holds that any such expression as 'that penny' applies distributively to every member of a whole class of particulars. Some of these have characteristics of one kind, and some have characteristics of another kind; but each has characteristics of only one kind. Again, the characteristics of each (other than its date and position) are relatively indeterminate.

      Now, on the former view of physical objects, any visual prehensum which could be identified with even a part of the surface of a physical object would differ profoundly in its intrinsic nature from any which could not. But, on Marc-Wogau's view of physical objects, there is no reason why there should be any intrinsic difference between those visual prehensa which are, and those which are not in the strictest sense, identifiable with the seen physical object.

      What the Argument from Continuity shows is that it is unreasonable to divide the objects which are visually prehended when the same object is viewed from different positions and in different directions into two classes of intrinsically different kinds of objects. Whether it does or does not follow that it is unreasonable to divide them into those which can, and those which cannot, be identified with the seen physical object or parts of its surface, is another question. And the answer to it will depend on the view which one takes about the nature of visible physical objects and the relation of visual prehensa to them.

(D) Argument from Certainty and Uncertainty about Existence.

      Marc-Wogau's statement and criticism of this argument will be found on pages 253 to 257 of his book. I shall begin by stating the argument in my own way. It may be put as follows.

     

  1. Whenever a person ostensibly sees a physical object answering to a certain description he is undoubtedly visually prehending something. This prehensum is commonly called a 'visual sense-datum', and there is no doubt that it exists while it is being prehended.
  2. It is always possible to doubt whether a physical object exists and is before the eyes of the percipient, answering to the description of the physical object which he is ostensibly seeing. It is possible on occasion for the percipient himself to doubt this while he is having the ostensible perception. (E.g., this might well happen to an intelligent and critical person who had an illness in which he was delirious at times with lucid intervals between.)
  3. If it is at the same time possible for a person to doubt the existence of O and impossible for him to doubt the existence of Ω. O must be numerically different from Ω.
  4. Therefore, even if the ostensible perception should be completely veridical, the sense-datum which is sensed must be different from the physical object which is perceived.

      According to Marc-Wogau the argument involves a fallacy of ambiguity. In Proposition (i) 'exists' must be used in sense E1. In Proposition (ii) it must be used in sense E3. But Proposition (iii) is true only if 'exists' is used in the same sense of both O and Ω.

      In my opinion it is possible to restate the argument without bringing in the word 'exist'; but I believe the argument to be fallacious for other reasons. I will now restate it and criticise it in its modified form.

      Let us take a concrete case of a person who is ostensibly seeing a penny under the most favourable conditions, i.e., the sort of conditions under which Marc-Wogau would hold that he is visually prehending the penny. The argument may be put as follows.

  1. He cannot doubt that there is an object possessing the characteristics which he visually prehends his prehensum as having, e.g., an object answering to the description 'round-looking, brown-looking, flat-looking object in the middle of my present visual field'.
  2. He can doubt whether there is an object answering to the description of the physical object which he is ostensibly seeing. E.g., he can doubt whether there is an object answering to the description 'object which is circular and brown and hard and smooth and made of copper, which would be visible and tangible to other people, and which is now reflecting light to my eyes'.
  3. If a person can be sure that there is an object answering to one description, and cannot be sure that there is an object answering to another description, the two descriptions cannot apply to the same object.
  4. Therefore the visual prehensum must differ numerically from the seen physical object even when the visual prehension is completely veridical.

      I think it is plain that this argument is fallacious, and that the fallacy lies in Proposition (iii). It is surely plain that two descriptions might in fact apply to the same object, and yet a person might know that one of them applied to a certain object and be quite uncertain whether the other applied to the same object or to any object at all. E.g., I am quite certain that there was a person answering to the description given in the Dictionary of National Biography under the entry 'Sir Philip Francis'. I am uncertain whether he or anyone else answers to the description 'the author of the Letters of Junius'. For those letters may have been written by several persons, in which case there is no-one answering to the description 'the author of the Letters of Junius'. And, even if all were written by the same person, he may not have been Francis. Nevertheless it is quite possible that the two descriptions do in fact apply to the same person; and most experts are inclined to think it very likely that they do.

      There is in fact nothing in the argument unless we add the following premise. 'If an object is prehended as having certain characteristics, it cannot have (and it cannot be a part of the surface of an object which has) any other characteristics. In particular, if it is visually prehended, it cannot have (and cannot be a part of the surface of an object which has) any characteristics which could not be visually prehended'. I have already considered this premiss, and have said that it simply begs the question at issue.

      This is perhaps the best place to consider the question 'Can a Sense-datum appear to be otherwise than it really is? which Marc-Wogau discusses elaborately on pages 257 to 273 of his book. It seems to me that the alternatives need to be stated more systematically, and I shall begin by trying to do this.

      Let us suppose that a certain prehensum has in fact the two determinable characteristics B&C, and no others, and that it has them respectively in the perfectly determinate forms b and c. Then the following alternatives seem to be abstractly possible.

  1. That it might be prehended as having b&c&d, where d is a perfectly determinate form of a determinable D which it does not in fact possess.
  2. That it might be prehended as having b&c', where c' is a different determinate form of C from the form c which in fact belongs to it.
  3. That it might be prehended as having b&γ, where γ is a not completely determinate form of C, and c falls under γ.
  4. That it might be prehended as having b&γ', where γ' is a not completely determinate form of C, and c falls outside of γ'.
  5. That it might be sensed as having b, and not as having any determinate under C.

      I will give an example of each alternative. We will suppose that the prehensum is in fact scarlet and equilaterally triangular and that it has no temperature.

  1. It is prehended as scarlet, equilaterally triangular, and cold.
  2. It is prehended as equilaterally triangular and sky-blue.
  3. It is prehended as equilaterally triangular and red, but not as scarlet or as any other perfectly determinate shade of red.
  4. It is prehended as equilaterally triangular and blue, but not as any perfectly determinate shade of blue.
  5. It is prehended as scarlet, but not as having shape.

      In Cases (1), (2), and (4) there would be positive error. They could all be described as 'prehending the object as having a characteristic which it does not in fact have'. But there is an important difference between Case (1) and Cases (2) and (4). In Case (1) the object is prehended as having a characteristic which, though not in fact present, would not be incompatible with those which are present. In Cases (2) and (4) the characteristic which is erroneously prehended as present is incompatible with some of those which are present. The error here is one of dislocation, not one of mere unwarranted addition.

      Marc-Wogau considers only two alternatives, which we will call A and B. His A covers my Cases (1), (2) and (4); his B covers my Cases (3) and (5). He labours to show that the former do not differ essentially from the latter. I remain quits unconvinced. It seems to me that there is an enormous difference. In Cases (3) and (5) there is no error, there is only inadequacy. In Case (3) the inadequacy is that the quality which the object is prehended as having is less determinate than, though inclusive of, that which it actually has. In Case (5) the inadequacy is that one fails to prehend the object as having in any form a quality which it in fact has in a certain determinate form. In Cases (1), (2) and (4), as I have said, there would be positive error. They are all instances of misprehension, taking the form either of unwarranted addition or of dislocation. Now I have no difficulty whatever in supposing that one may prehend an object inadequately in sense (3); i.e., as having the determinable C in a certain incompletely determinate form γ, when in fact it has C in a certain perfectly determinate form α which falls under γ. I have very little difficulty in supposing that one may prehend an object inadequately in sense (5); i.e., that one might fail to prehend it as having in any form a certain determinable C which it in fact has in a certain perfectly determinate form c. But I find it almost impossible to conceive that one could misprehend an object in either of the senses (1), (2) or (4); and I do not find less difficulty in any one of them than in any other.

(E) Argument from Covariance.

      The essential premise of this argument is that there is concomitant variation between changes in the medium, the position, the physiological and psychological state of the percipient, etc., on the one hand, and the determinate characteristics which the prehensum is prehended as having, on the other. From this it is inferred, in the first instance, that the seen physical object (or rather a certain imperceptible process in it) is at best one factor in a rather remote causal ancestor of the visual sensation by which it manifests itself to the percipient. From this the following two conclusions are drawn, often without any explicit recognition of the fact that they are further inferences and require additional premisses.

  1. That the visual prehensum, so far from being identical with the seen physical object or with a part of its surface, is a product of a long process of causation in which the seen physical object is at most a remote contributory cause-factor.
  2. That it is unreasonable to ascribe to the seen physical object any of those determinable qualities, such as colour, which the visual prehensum is prehended as having.

      I shall first summarise Marc-Wogau's criticisms of such arguments in general. These occur on pages 143 to 145 of his book. Then I shall consider in detail two particular arguments of this form, and his criticisms on them.

      Marc-Wogau's general criticisms are as follows.

  1. Many of the arguments tacitly assume that one is justified in ascribing to the seen physical object only those qualities which, if they were present, would inevitably be perceived to be present in it. There is nothing self-evident in this principle, whether 'inevitably' be understood in the sense of logical, or of merely causal, necessity.
  2. If I am in doubt whether an object, which I ostensibly see, really exists or not, it will generally be relevant to enquire whether my visual experience was or was not evoked by light-waves emitted from the place at which I ostensibly see it. But this will not enable me to decide what sensible qualities do, and what do not, belong to the seen object unless I already ascribe, independently of causal considerations, certain sensible qualities to physical objects.
  3. No conclusion as to whether sensible qualities do or do not belong to physical objects can be drawn merely from the covariance between changes in the sensible qualities prehended by an observer and changes in his body, in the medium, and so on. All that follows is that the sensation, which in fact occurred under certain conditions, would have differed in certain respects if the conditions had differed in certain respects.
  4. The difficulties which would arise, if we supposed that every quality which anyone prehends under any conditions belongs to the perceived physical object, can be met without supposing that no quality which anyone prehends under any conditions ever belongs to the perceived physical object.
  5. It is much more plausible to make sounds and smells all subjective than to do this with colours and forms. But it is no proof of the subjectivity of sound to show that it is localized, not only in the sonorous object, but also in the surrounding air and in the hearer's head.

      The two particular arguments which I shall consider are (1) an argument about colour which Marc-Wogau ascribes to Lord Russell, and (2) an argument from the finite velocity of light.

(1) Russell's Argument about Colour.

      This argument is taken from Problems of Philosophy. It is discussed by Marc-Wogau on pages 139 to 143 of his book. I shall begin by restatmg the argument in my own way.

      Suppose that a person is looking at a certain object at a certain moment t. For a given state of his eye, brain, and nervous system the colour which he then perceives that object to have is correlated one-to-one with the wave-length of the light which enters his eye at t from that object. But the wave-length of that light is not correlated one-to-one with that of the light which left the object at t', where t-t' is the time taken by light to travel from the object to the eye. For the former depends jointly on the latter and on the state of the intervening medium during the period t - t'. On the other hand, the wave-length of the light which left the object at t' is correlated one-to-one with a certain state of the object at t'. Let us call that state σt'. It follows that the colour which the observer at t perceives the object to have is not correlated one-to-one with that state σt', of the object which is uniquely correlated with the wave-length of the light emitted by the object at t'.

      I think it is plain that, if the premisses are all admitted, this is the utmost that can be drawn from them alone. Now the conclusion which Russell actually draws is that it is unreasonable to ascribe colours to physical objects. Plainly he must be tacitly assuming some additional premiss about colour and its connexion or disconnexion with physical objects. Marc-Wogau says that the premise is that physical objects have objective colours. He then accuses Russell of contradicting himself by using this premiss to prove the conclusion that it is unreasonable to ascribe objective colours to physical objects.

      I believe this objection to be fallacious. It does not appear to me that Russell would have contradicted himself even if this were the premiss which he tacitly assumes. This can easily be shown as follows. Let p be the proposition 'physical objects have objective colours'. Let the conjunction of all the other premisses be P. Then at worst what Russell would have claimed to show is that p&P entails not-p. Now this is equivalent to 'P entails that p materially implies not-p'. But 'p materially implies not-p' entails not-p. So we reach the conclusion that P entails not-p. That is precisely what Russell wants to prove. There is certainly no formal fallacy here.

      The above is, however, an over-simplification of Russell's argument. It should rather, I think, be put in the following form. 'If we combine the supposition that physical objects have objective colours with the premisses which have been explicitly mentioned and asserted, it follows that this supposition is unreasonable. But the premisses are true. Therefore, if the supposition is made, it must be combined with them. Therefore the supposition is unreasonable.' I can see nothing logically amiss with this type of argument.

      Let us now revert to the argument as I stated it at the beginning of this discussion. The missing premiss is 'The state σt' of an object which is uniquely correlated with the wave-length of the light which it emits at t' is its objective colour'. As I have said, this premise, unlike the others, is not accepted categorically as true; it is entertained hypothetically as a supposition to be tested. If we combine it with the other premisses, the conclusion which immediately follows is 'If a physical object has an objective colour, that colour is not uniquely correlated with the one which the observer prehends when he looks at it'.

      That is a very tame conclusion, and it is not the one which Russell draws. In order to justify the latter we must add another premiss, and this must be asserted categorically and not merely entertained hypothetically as a supposition. It is the proposition 'Unless the objective colour of a perceived object were uniquely correlated with the colour which an observer prehends when he looks at it, it would be unreasonable to suppose that it has any colour at all'.

      I do not think that Russell would expect us to swallow this premiss whole. I think that we are expected to make the following two bites at it. (i) 'Unless the objective colour of a perceived object were uniquely correlated with the colour which an observer prehends when he looks at it, it would be unreasonable to ascribe to the object any one determinate colour rather than any other. (ii) 'If it would be unreasonable to ascribe to a perceived object any one determinate colour rather than any other, it would be unreasonable to suppose that it had any objective colour.'

      I agree with Marc-Wogau in finding neither of these premisses very plausible when they are explicitly formulated. As regards the first, I should say that we draw a distinction between certain states of the medium, of the illumination, of the observer's body, etc., and others. We should say that it is reasonable to ascribe to a perceived object an objective colour identical with, or not very different from, that which a normal observer prehends when he views it by daylight through a clear colourless medium. As regards the second, I should say that it might be accepted in the abstract, though without much conviction; but that, unless the first be granted, it leads nowhere.

      I gather that Marc-Wogau would accept these remarks. He also casts doubt on the premiss that, for a given state of the brain and nervous system, the colour prehended is correlated one-to-one with the wave-length of the light that strikes the eye. According to him, accurate phenomenological observations show that there is a range within which the latter may vary without any correlated variation in the former.

(2) Argument from the finite Velocity of Light.

      I shall first state this argument in my own way and then consider Marc-Wogau's counter-arguments.

      Suppose that, throughout the period from t1 to t2, a person sees a certain physical object O. Let us imagine the process of seeing to consist of a continuous series of successive instantaneous acts. Consider the instantaneous act which takes place at an instant t, intermediate between t1 and t2. Let the distance of the object from the observer be d, and let the velocity of light in the intervening medium be c. (We shall assume for simplicity that the distance remains constant throughout the period under consideration.) Then the stimulus which called forth the instantaneous act at t was the light which then reached the obscrver's eye from O. This left O at t - d/c. Now the prehensum is strictly simultaneous with the act of prehending it. Therefore the prehensum which is prehended at t is something which exists at t and then only. On the other hand, the physical object O may have ceased to exist altogether between the instant t - d/c, when it emitted the light which reaches the percipient at t, and the instant t, when that light reaches him. Now (i) we cannot identify something which certainly exists at t with something which may nevertheless have ceased to exist at t. Again (ii) the characteristics which the prehensum is prehended as having depend on the nature of the light which calls forth the sensation. But the nature of that light is a causal descendant of the characteristics which O had at the instant t - d/c, when the light was emitted from it. Even if O still exis3ts and the intervening medium be homogeneous and colourless, these characteristics may have changed by the time t when the light reaches the percipient's eye. So at best the characteristics which the prehensum is prehended as having are those which the seen physical object had at an earlier date.

      It should be noted that Marc-Wogau does not state the argument so fully as I have done, and in particular that he does not divide the conclusion into two parts. He has three counterarguments. I find the first of these very obscure. I shall therefore have to state in my own way what I suppose to be the first counter-argument.

      (i) This counter-argument certainly turns on the notion of a literally instantaneous act of prehension, which occurs in the argument stated above. Marc-Wogau says that a certain duration must be ascribed both to the act of prehending and to the prehensum. But he seems to me to give two different reasons for this, and not to notice that they are different.

      One reason alleged is that 'the light-stimulus must act unchanged during a certain period if the percipient is to perceive anything, and in particular if he is to ascribe to what he perceives existence in the sense in which physical objects are ordinarily said to exist'. The other reason is a reference to what psychologists call the 'specious present', and to the fact that this is not instantaneous but has a short finite duration. Unfortunately no clear account is given of that very obscure subject, the doctrine of the specious present. In any case it seems to me certain that Marc-Wogau is alluding to two different facts, whether or not he thinks that he is doing so. The first is concerned with the relation between stimulus and sensation; the second, so far as I can see, has nothing to do with stimulus. Let us call the two alleged facts 'persistence of stimulus' and 'finite duration of specious present'.

      I believe that both these alleged facts are needed for Marc-Wogau's argument. I shall first explain what I understand by the two alleged facts, and shall then try to state what I suppose to be the essence of the argument.

      (a) I understand by the doctrine of the persistence of stimulus that, if an act of visual prehension is to take place at the instant t, a light-stimulus must have been acting on the percipient for a short period σ, which stretches back from t to t - σ. (b) I understand by the doctrine of the finite duration of the specious present that the object of an instantaneous act of prehension occurring at t, is not itself instantaneous but stretches back from t for a short period τ to t - τ.

      The argument, on my interpretation of it, would now run as follows. The stimulus which evokes the act of prehension at t is the light emitted by O during the period from t - σ - d/c to t - d/c. (This is because of the persistence of stimulus.) The prehensum which is prehended at t stretches back from t to l - τ. (This is because of the finite duration of the specious present.) Therefore, provided that τ > d/c, the earlier phase of the prehensum will overlap in time with the later part of the period during which O is emitting the light which evokes the prehension at t. This will be quite clear from the diagram below.

So, provided that d/c is small in comparison with t, there is no objection to identifying the earlier phase of the prehensum which is prehended at t with the physical object as it was during the later part of the period throughout which it was emitting that train of waves whose cumulative effect was to evoke the prehension at t.

      Again, it is alleged that the light-stimulus must have been of the same nature throughout the period σ if the percipient is to 'ascribe to what he perceives existence in the sense in which physical objects are said to exist'. (I take this to mean 'if he is to see the object, not as a mere coloured flash, but as a material thing, such as a table'.) On that assumption there is no objection in principle to assuming that the characteristics which the prehensum is prehended at t as having are the same as those which the physical object had throughout the period which ends at t - d/c.

      I feel sure that this must be the kind of argument which Marc-Wogau has in mind in the very condensed and rather obscure passage on pages 63 to 64, but it is possible that he would not accept my reconstruction in detail. It will be noticed that, in my account of the argument, I talk of an instantaneous act of prehending, whilst Marc-Wogau says that a finite duration must be ascribed to any act of prehending. I do not think that there is any real difference of opinion here, or that the argument has been prejudiced in any way. I agree that any actual experience is a process and takes time, and that 'instantaneous acts' (like 'the position of a moving body at an instant') are fictions. But that is no reason why one should not consider a cross-section of such a process at a certain instant, as I have done. I do not think that it is at all easy to give an intelligible account of the doctrine of the specious present except in terms of such a cross-section.

      It will be noted that a condition for the applicability of this counter-argument is that the time d/c, taken by the light to travel from the object to the percipient, shall be less than τ, the duration of his specious present. Marc-Wogau says, quite truly, that this condition is fulfilled in the case of all objects in the percipient's neighbourhood. He adds that these are the only objects to which the argument which he is trying to refute applies. I cannot understand why he believes this. I should have thought that we identify (or, better, fail to distinguish) the visual prehensum and the seen physical object in the case of the sun, e.g., where the condition certainly does not hold.

      (ii) Marc-Wogau's second counter-argument consists in questioning the premise that the act of prehending and the prehensum are exactly contemporary. He says that he sees no reason why there should not be a 'certain vanishingly small time-difference between the two' without the experience ceasing to be perceptual and taking on the character of memory.

      I have two comments to make on this. (a) If we allow for the finite duration of the specious present, both the premiss about simultaneity in the original argument and Marc-Wogau's exception to it will need to be stated more carefully. The premiss can be restated as follows. 'If an instantaneous act of prehension takes place at t and its prehensum has the duration τ, then t is situated either at the last moment or the first moment of τ or at some moment intermediate between these two.' Marc-Wogau's contention is that the last moment of τ may precede t by a small finite amount. (b) My second comment is that in many cases a vanishingly short gap will not help Marc-Wogau to answer the argument. Cf. again the case of seeing the sun.

      (iii) Marc-Wogau's third counter-argument consists in questioning the premise that, if the characteristics which the prehensum is prehended as having correspond to those of the physical object seen, they correspond to those which it had when the light left it, and not (except by chance) to those which it has when that light reaches the percipient.

      In the argument, as stated by me above, this premiss appears as the result of two others, viz., (α) that the characteristics which the prehensum is prehended as having depend on the nature of the light which calls forth the act of prehending it; and (β) that the nature of that light is a causal descendant of the characteristics which the physical object had at the moment when the light was emitted from it. Of course a third premiss is also tacitly assumed, viz., (γ) that the nature of the light has not changed during the process of transmission. Marc-Wogau's countersuggestion is that, although no events in O after the instant t - d/c are causally relevant to the occurrence at t of the act of prehension in the percipient, yet the prehensuwn of that act may have characteristics which correspond to those which O has at t, and not to those which it had at t - d/c.

      As regards this suggestion I can only say that, taken in isolation, it is logically possible; but that there is a large mass of very varied empirical facts which would be very hard to reconcile with it and which all fit neatly into the premisses of the original argument. I have dealt with some of these, e.g., the phenomenon of aberration, in my Scientific Thought. In general, I think that Marc-Wogau's counter-arguments here have the air of desperate special-pleading. If I knew the Swedish equivalent of the English saying 'Pigs might fly!', I should be tempted to quote it to him. To my mind these counter-arguments do little if anytlling, to weaken the effect of the argument against which they are directed.